Ramkrishna Bhattacharya
Cārvāka:
The Base Text and Its Commentators from the Eighth Century
We now
come to the formation of the philosophical systems, each having a set of
aphorisms or sūtras with commentaries and sub-commentaries. Broadly
speaking, the brahmanical position was unsparing in denouncing all the three of
its non-Vedic adversaries, while the materialists had to put up a lone battle
against all philosophical systems, Vedic and non-Vedic, but mostly against
Buddhism, Jainism, Nyāya, and Vedānta. While the writings of the pre-Cārvāka
materialist schools are unavailable, some fragments of the new, Cārvāka, school
have come down to us. They can be divided into three kinds: (a) aphorisms (sūtras)
and pseudo-aphorisms, (b) extracts from commentaries to the aphorisms, and (c) verses
attributed to the Cārvākas[i]. The book
of aphorisms was most probably compiled by Purandara, who is also credited with
writing a short commentary (vṛtti). Besides the aphorisms that can be
safely admitted as genuine, some others are of dubious authenticity. The
distinction is made on the basis of the fact that some aphorisms are found
quoted in
several works with more or less the same wording. Those which occur only once
may be marked as pseudo-aphorisms. The names of four commentators on the
Cārvāka sūtras have so far come to light. They are Bhāvaviveka,
Kambalāśvatara (“blanket-mule,” most probably a nickname), Aviddhakarṇa (“whose
ear is not pierced,” probably another nickname), and Udbhaṭa-bhaṭṭa or Bhaṭṭodbhaṭa.
That the Cārvāka system, very much like other systems, did not remain unaltered
but saw its own development is borne out by the interpretation of some of the
aphorisms offered by commentators in or around the eighth century[ii].
Udbhaṭa
is the last of the commentators known to us. Jayanta and Cakradhara both speak
of “old (cirantana) Cārvāka” and recent Cārvākas like Udbhaṭa. Udbhaṭa
goes against the literal meaning of the aphorisms; he twists the meaning of words,
which are made, almost under duress, to conform to the meanings preferred by
him. In many respects he may be called a revisionist among the Cārvākas.
However, what unites Purandara, Aviddhakarṇa, and Udbhaṭa is their assertion that,
although inference based on perception can provide knowledge, inference based
on authority (āpta) and verbal testimony (śabda or āptavākya)
are inadmissible. So any statement concerning the existence of heaven and hell,
god, an omniscient person, and so on is open to question. According to all of
them, inference per se is not an independent instrument of cognition.
Aviddhakarṇa and Udbhaṭa between themselves provide a number of arguments, both
subtle and to the
point, to establish this stand. Thus the extreme empiricism associated with
older formulations of materialism is ameliorated by Cārvāka thinkers.
Here
are the Cārvāka aphorisms (sūtras).
Materialism
I.1 We
shall now explain the principle.
I.2 Earth,
water, fire, and air are the principles, nothing else.
I.3 Their combination
is called the “body,” “sense,” and “object.”
I.4 Consciousness
(arises or is manifested) out of these.
I.5 As the
power of intoxication (arises or is manifested from the constituent parts of
the wine (such as flour, water, and molasses).
I.6 The
self is (nothing but) the body endowed with consciousness.
I.7 From
the body itself.
+ I.8 Because
of the existence (of consciousness) where there is a body.
I.9 Souls
are like water bubbles.
COMP
Please provide line spacing here and for the below instances.?>
The
doctrine of inherent nature (svabhāva; lit. own being)
II.1 The
world is varied due to the variation of origin.
II.2 As the
eye in the peacock’s tail.
The
doctrine of the primacy of perception
III.1 Perception
indeed is the (only) means of right knowledge.
III.2 Since
the means of right knowledge is to be non-secondary, it is difficult to
ascertain an object by means of inference.
The
doctrine of the denial of rebirth and the other-world
IV.1 There
is no means of knowledge for determining (the existence of) the other-world.
IV.2 There
is no other-world because of the absence of any other-worldly being (i.e., the
transmigrating self).
IV.3 Due to
the insubstantiality of consciousness (residing in the other-world).
The
doctrine of the uselessness of performing religious acts
V.1 Religious
act is not to be performed.
V.2 Its
(religion’s) instructions are not to be relied upon.
In
addition to the aphorisms, verses, typically attributed to the pūraṇic Bṛhaspati,
are mostly of the nature of what Patañjali would call “sung while intoxicated,”
pramatta-gīta[iii].
Only three of the ten and half verses quoted by Mādhava in the Compendium
of All Philosophies may be said properly to reflect the materialist view:
There
is no heaven, no final liberation, nor any soul in another world.Nor do
the actions of the four castes, orders, etc., produce any real effect.While
life remains let a man live happily; nothing is beyond death.When
once the body becomes ashes, how can it ever return again?If he
who departs from the body goes to another world,How is
it that he comes not back again, restless for love of his kindred?[iv]
Mādhava
refers to Bṛhaspati as the author of a number of verses that are found in the Viṣṇu
Purāṇa and in Buddhist and Jaina sources[v]. Buddhists
and Jainas share some of the views of the Cārvākas. As we have seen, all the
three were branded “negativists” by Vedists. Dharmakīrti, conversely, says of
Vedism/brahmanism, that “Belief in the authority of the Vedas, and in some
creator (of the world), desiring merit from bathing, pride in (high) caste, and
practicing self-denial for the eradication of sins—these five are the marks of
stupidity of one whose intelligence is damaged.”[vi] All three
groups oppose most particularly the performance of annual rituals for departed
ancestors (śrāddha) and sacrificial rites (yajña) with a view to
fulfilling one’s heart’s desire, both in this world and the next. But the
opposition of the two religious communities on the one hand and the Cārvākas on
the other arose from different reasons[vii]. The
Cārvākas deny something that is axiomatic to the Buddhists and Jainas, the
doctrines of karma and rebirth. Since Cārvākas do not consider philosophy to be
a means of emancipation from the cycle of rebirth (mokṣa, mukti, or nirvāṇa)
but view it as a practical guide to life, they incurred the wrath of all
believers in the other-world, brahmanical or otherwise. The Cārvākas do not
think in terms of the four aims of life (puruṣārthas), namely, religious
merit (dharma), wealth (artha), pleasure (kāma), and
freedom (mokṣa); and this too marks them apart from others.
What
the opponents of the Cārvāka make them say regarding caste (varṇa) and
women deserves attention. They are represented as being opposed to caste discrimination
and in favor of the equality of women and men. This representation (censorial
in intention) is borne out by the heretical views attributed to Kāli,
personification of the Iron Age, in Śrīharṣa’s Life of Naiṣadha:
Since
purity of caste is possible only in the case of purity on each side of both
families of the grandparents, what caste is pure by the purity of limitless
generations? Fie on
those who boast of family dignity! They hold women in check out of jealousy;
but do not likewise restrain men, though the blindness of passion is common to
both! Spurn
all censorious statements about women as not worth a straw. Why dost thou
constantly cheat people when thou, too, art as bad as women?[viii]
That
this is not an isolated case or a mere figment of Śrīharṣa’s imagination is
borne out by similar representations found elsewhere.[ix]
Cārvākas
have often been accused of unrestrained hedonism. While such Buddhist, Jaina,
and brahmanical opponents of the Lokāyata as Śāntarakṣita, Prabhācandra, and Śaṅkara
preferred to controvert materialism solely on logical and epistemological
grounds, some others condemned it for being licentious. It is worth noting that
similar equation of materialism and hedonism has also been made in relation to
Epicurus (341–270 BCE), though he is known to have led an extremely frugal life[x]. As with
Epicurus, so with the Cārvākas: there is not an iota of evidence to prove that
they used to preach an “eat, drink, and be merry” kind of philosophy, nor is
there is a single aphorism that advises people to indulge in sensual
gratification. As with Epicurus again, the Cārvākas might nevertheless have
declared pleasure to be the aim of life. A popular verse runs as follows:
While
life is yours, live joyously;None
can escape Death’s searching eye;When
once this frame of ours they burn,How
should it e’er again return?[xi]
We
know from Epicurus’s own words that by pleasure he meant intellectual
enjoyment, not eating and living like a pig—which is what Horace unjustly said
of him. Jayanta, no friend of the Cārvākas, says of “Live joyously” that “being
naturally established, a prescription in this regard becomes useless.”[xii] The
available fragments of the commentaries on the Cārvāka-sūtra clearly
reveal their authors’ acumen as logicians, and to think that they could lead
the life of debauchees boggles the mind.
Bibliography
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. Studies on the Cārvāka/Lokāyata. Firenze: Società Editriche Fiorentina, 2009; London: Anthem Press, 2011.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “The Social Outlook of the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Reconstruction.” Indologica Taurinensia 36 (2010): 37–42.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “The Wolf’s Footprints: Indian Materialism in Perspective.” Interview with Krishna Del Toso. Annali 71 (2011): 183–204.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “Svabhāvavāda and the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Historical Overview.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 40, no. 5 (2012): 593–614.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “Verses Attributed to Bṛhaspati in the Sarvadarśanasaṃgraha: A Critical Appraisal.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 615–630.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad. In Defence of Materialism in Ancient India. New Delhi: People’s Publishing House, 1989.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad, and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, eds. Cārvāka/Lokāyata. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990.
Dixit, K. K. “The Ideological Affiliation of Jayarāśi—The Author of Tattvopaplavasiṃha.” In Cārvāka/Lokāyata, edited by D. Chattopadhyaya and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, pp. 520–530. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990.
Franco, Eli: Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarāśi’s Scepticism. Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi 1994; 1st edition, Alt- und Neu-Indische Studien 35, Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1987.
Jayarāśibhaṭṭa. Tattvopaplavasiṃha of Jayarāśibhaṭṭa. Tr. Esther Solomon; ed. Shuchita Mehta: Jayarāśi Bhaṭṭa’s Tattvopaplavasiṁha. An Introduction, Sanskrit Text, English Translation and Notes. Parimal Sanskrit Series 111. Delhi: Parimal Publications, 2010.
Saṁghavī, Sukhlāljī; Pārīkh, Rasiklāl C., eds. Tattvopaplavasimha of Shri Jayarasi Bhatta. Edited with an introduction and indices. Gaekwad Oriental Series 87, Baroda: Oriental Institute, 1940; reprinted, Bauddha Bharati Series 20, Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1987.
[i]
For details see R. Bhattacharya, Studies on the Cārvāka/Lokāyata, chap. 6.
[ii]
Kamalaśīla, TSP
verse 1864, mentions two
approaches to the interpretation of an aphorism that contains no verb. One
commentator supplied the verb “is born” after the subject, so that it reads
“consciousness is born of these (elements),” while another commentator
explained the same aphorism as “consciousness is
manifested from these (elements).” Since
Kamalaśīla uses the plural in case of both, it is not clear
whether he means two individual commentators (the plural being honorific) or
two groups of commentators (each group having some adherents of its own). As no
names are mentioned it is impossible to decide who Kamalaśīla
had in mind.
[iii]
Kshitish Chandra Chatterji ed., Patañjali’s Mahābhāṣya.
Paśpaśāhnika with English translation (Calcutta: A. Mukherjee &
Co., 1972), K. V. Abhyankar and Jaydev Mohanlal Shukla ed., Patañjali’s VyakaraHa-Mahabha+ya, Ahnikas (Pune: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1975),
1–3. Patañjali, Mahābhāṣya, chap.1, Calcutta ed. 18, Pune ed. 13.
[iv]
Sāyaṇa-Mādhava, Sarvadarśanasangraha. ed. K. L. Joshi. (Ahmedabad/Delhi: Parimal
Publication, 1981), V. Shastri Abhyankar ed. (Pune: Bhandarkar Oriental
Research Institute, 1978) (reprint).
[v]
See R. Bhattacharya, “Verses Attributed to Bṛhaspati
in the Sarvadarśanasaṃgraha: A Critical Appraisal,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 615–630.
[vi]
Dharmakīrti, auto-commentary on the Pramāṇa-Vārttika, chap. 1 (Ilahabad: Kitab Mahal, 1943), 617–618.
[vii]
Both the rites involved slaying of animals, which was
anathema to the doctrine of non-injury (ahiṃsā)
of the Buddhists and the Jains. The Cārvākas too were opposed to
postmortem rites, for they regarded them as useless (since there can be no life
after death) and no benefit can accrue from the performance of yajñas,
for there were no gods to grant the sacrificers’ prayers. In spite of all this,
the two religious communities clung to the idea of rebirth, after-life (paraloka)
and the mysterious effects of karman
and adṛṣṭa.
[viii]
Śrīharṣa,
Life of Naiṣadha
17. 40, 42, 58. Naiṣadhacarita. ed. Sivadatta and V. L. Panshikar. (Mumbai: Nirnay
Sagar Press, 1928). K. K. Handiqui trans. (Pune: Deccan College Postgraduate
Research Institute, 1956).
[ix]
For details see R. Bhattacharya, “The Social Outlook
of the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Reconstruction,” Indologica Taurinensia 36 (2010): 37–42.
[x]
Horace, Epistles 1.4.16 in Epistles (London:
William Heinemann, 1926). See also Paul Harvey, Oxford Companion to Classical Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 162.
[xi]
Mādhava, Compendium
of All Philosophies. Pune ed., p. 2, lines 17–18.
[xii]
Jayantabhaṭṭa, Nyāyamañjarī,
part 1 (Varanasi: Sampurnanand Sanskrit Visvavidyalaya, 1982), 388, translated
in Cārvāka/Lokāyata, ed. D. Chattopadhyaya and M. K. Gangopadhyaya (New
Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990), 157.
Prof Ramkrishna Bhattacharya taught English at Unversity of Calcutta, Kolkota and was an Emeritus Fellow of University Grants Commission. He is now Fellow of Pavlov Institute, Kolkota
This essay is published in four parts:
Part I,
Part II, Part III, & Part IV