Tuesday, 30 August 2016

Science versus Miracles: Ideomotor Response and Pendulum Dowsing

B. Premanand

Whatever action we perform is controlled by the brain. If we have any thought or idea in the subconscious mind, when we concentrate on the same, it manifests as a physical activity without any conscious attempt by the person. This is called idiomotor response. The minute electrical charges in the brain transmit to the muscles through the nerves.

The persons who create motivating force through idiomotor response do not have any idea that they are the cause. It is these involuntary muscle movements, which cause the water divining stick to revolve and the planchet to work.

The following experiment will prove the effect of idiomotor response.

Experiment: 145


Effect: The pendulum moves in circle or a straight line when you concen­trate on a circle or a straight line.

Props: A pendulum suspended on a thread, a chair, and a table.

Method: Draw a circle of 6" diameter on a sheet of paper and through the centre of the circle draw a straight line. Sit on a chair holding the top end of the thread to which the pendulum is suspended resting your elbow on the table. If you hold the pendulum on the centre of the circle and let your eyes follow the straight line, gradually the pendulum will swing straight along the line.

If you let your eyes follow the circle clockwise and concentrate, the pendulum will start moving in a circle, clockwise. Then when again you follow the circle anti-clockwise the pendulum will start moving anti-clockwise in a circle.

Saturday, 27 August 2016

The Jayarāśi Question [A History of Materialism From Ajita to Udbhaṭa - Part IV]


Ramkrishna Bhattacharya   


The Jayarāśi Question

The Lion Assailing the Verities (Tattvopaplavasiṃha), written by Jayarāśi probably in the ninth century, has been claimed by some scholars to be the only surviving Cārvāka work. Others have challenged this view[i]. Since there is no external evidence to settle the question, the debate continues solely on the basis of internal evidence and intrinsic probability. No near-unanimous conclusion has been reached to date. Instead of summarizing the whole debate, a few issues are raised here. They go against branding Jayarāśi a Cārvāka, but identify him rather as a founder/follower of a totally new doctrine, which is quite distinct from both materialism on the one hand and any form of illusionism (māyāvāda) or nihilism (śūnyavāda) on the other. His is “the doctrine of assailing the verities,” tattvopaplava-vāda. This is the name used by Jayarāśi’s critics; nowhere is he called a Cārvāka or “one belonging to a section of the Cārvāka” (Cārvākaikadeśīya)[ii]. Although Jayarāśi is sometimes called a skeptic, there is little room for such a thing as doubt in his work. He is convinced that there can be no verities, tattvas, because there is no such thing as means of knowing, pramāṇa.

Now, Vātsyāyana in the exordium of his commentary to the Nyāya-sūtra, states that one has to admit not only the means of knowing, pramāṇa, but also knower (pramātṛ), the object rightly known (prameya), and knowledge of the object (pramiti): “With these four, tattva reaches its fulfillment.” Gangopadhyaya suggests that, in contrast with “the doctrine of assailing the verities,” Vātsyāyana’s view may be called “the doctrine of establishing the verities” (tattva-vyavasthāpanavāda)[iii]. It seems Vātsyāyana had a predecessor of Jayarāśi in mind, and against such an opponent he felt it necessary to assert all the four factors stated above, for this assertion can be understood only against the backdrop of an opponent who denies pramāṇa as such.

There is indeed a Cārvāka introduced at the very beginning of the The Lion Assailing the Verities. He is not Jayarāśi, but someone who is presented as a Cārvāka out to challenge Jayarāśi’s doctrine of upsetting principles as such. This objector has to be a Cārvāka, for who but a Cārvāka would refer to the basic premises of materialism and stand upon them? The presence of this objector and the way Jayarāśi gets into controversy with him clearly indicate that Jayarāśi himself was not a Cārvāka. He prided himself in claiming that he could understand Bṛhaspati’s sūtras better than the Cārvākas themselves, Jayarāśi referring to Bṛhaspati, the mythical guru of the gods, never to real-life philosophers like Purandara or Aviddhakarṇa, as Kamalaśīla, Karṇakagomin, Anantavīrya, Cakradhara, and Vādidevasūri do. Thus Jayarāśi supports the purāṇic story of the origin of materialism. At the end of his work he claims that 
Even those (questions) which could not become the object of knowledge of even the preceptor of the gods have been raised by Bhaṭṭa Śri Jayarāśi, for the sake of removing the pride of the infidels.[iv]

On the basis of this declaration, and the Cārvāka aphorisms quoted at the beginning of the work, he has been called a Bārhaspatya (follower of Bṛhaspati, the legendary founder of materialism) or a Cārvāka or Lokāyata. To this identification D. Chattopadhyaya objects that “[A]ccording to the Indian philosophical tradition no real representative of a system would ever dream of boasting intellectual superiority to the founder of the system itself. Jayarāśi, who claims to be intellectually
superior to Bṛhaspati, could thus hardly be a follower of Bṛhaspati himself, i.e., could hardly be the leader of any imaginary offshoot of the Cārvāka or Bārhaspatya system.”[v] Gangopadhyaya endorses this view and adds that “[t]he way Jayarāśi uses the honorific plural in mentioning his own name along with Bṛhaspati, bhaṭṭaśrījayarāśi-devagurubhiḥ …, places him in the seat of the preceptor of the gods, which goes against the Indian tradition. Jayarāśi further claims that all his opponents will be defeated by his arguments. This too is not the style of the explicators of Indian philosophy. The way of writing of later writers, even if they express views of their own, is suave and modest, as if they mean to suggest that this significance was inherent in the text itself.”[vi]

So, in conclusion, we have seen that materialism in India is not one homogeneous school. On the contrary, there have been several materialist schools through the ages. The Cārvākas (fl. c. eighth century) are the last school known to us. As with older materialisms, this new materialism too, after a long and turbulent period with refutation and counter-refutation stretching from the eighth century to the twelfth or thereabouts, seems to vanish. Like the extinction of species, both the pre-Cārvākas and the Cārvākas, with all their primary and secondary works once current from Kashmir to the regions beyond the Vindhya hills, disappear without trace. Even the oft-used doxographical work, Mādhava’s Compendium of All Philosophies, marked by profuse quotations in its exposition of all other philosophical systems, offers no direct quote from any commentary, nor does it even name any adherent of the Cārvāka in its terse summary of the system. The authors of other doxographical works appear to have no access to any primary or even secondary source; they merely echo or refer to those earlier opponents of the materialist system in whose works their views are quoted or paraphrased. The doxographers merely reproduce a few aphorisms and verses of dubious origin that have been quoted and re-quoted many times before. The pundits of north India who in the sixteenth century provided Abūl Fażl with the material concerning some of the philosophical systems fare no better. None of the other compendia refers to a single author or work, although we have several such names and even extracts quoted from their works written before the twelfth century.

The situation is partly similar to what happened to the Presocratics. Time, and lack of continuity due to the absence of disciples, may be held responsible for the unavailability of the works of Thales and Anaximander, of Democritus and Heraclitus, although they are known to have composed an impressive number of books. The rise of Plato and Aristotle as the two most influential philosophers, each having his school and a number of brilliant students to carry on their works, may also be the reason why the works of their predecessors and contemporaries have not survived[vii]. The Cārvāka could and did withstand the onslaught of Śaṅkara and Madhva, two influential Vedāntic philosophers who had a large following even after their deaths. As to the conjecture of a deliberate destruction of all materialist works by some unknown agency, royal or brahmanical, proposed by some scholars[viii], there is no evidence to support it. On the other hand, the fate of Āryabhaṭa’s geo-kinetic theory amply bears out the fact that another way of damning any contrary opinion is not to exterminate it, but to alter the text in an extremely subtle manner and misinterpret it deliberately so as to blunt its edge[ix]. At the present state of knowledge, the disappearance of the Cārvāka is as inexplicable as the disappearance of the old Sāṃkhya and old Lokāyata as enunciated by Brahman, Gargya and others.[x]


Bibliography

Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. Studies on the Cārvāka/Lokāyata. Firenze: Società Editriche Fiorentina, 2009; London: Anthem Press, 2011.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “The Social Outlook of the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Reconstruction.” Indologica Taurinensia 36 (2010): 37–42.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “The Wolf’s Footprints: Indian Materialism in Perspective.” Interview with Krishna Del Toso. Annali 71 (2011): 183–204.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “Svabhāvavāda and the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Historical Overview.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 40, no. 5 (2012): 593–614.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “Verses Attributed to Bṛhaspati in the Sarvadarśanasaṃgraha: A Critical Appraisal.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 615–630.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad. In Defence of Materialism in Ancient India. New Delhi: People’s Publishing House, 1989.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad, and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, eds. Cārvāka/Lokāyata. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990.
Dixit, K. K. “The Ideological Affiliation of Jayarāśi—The Author of Tattvopaplavasiṃha.” In Cārvāka/Lokāyata, edited by D. Chattopadhyaya and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, pp. 520–530. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990.
Franco, Eli: Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarāśi’s Scepticism. Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi 1994; 1st edition, Alt- und Neu-Indische Studien 35, Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1987.
Jayarāśibhaṭṭa. Tattvopaplavasiṃha of Jayarāśibhaṭṭa. Tr. Esther Solomon; ed. Shuchita Mehta: Jayarāśi Bhaṭṭa’s Tattvopaplavasiṁha. An Introduction, Sanskrit Text, English Translation and Notes. Parimal Sanskrit Series 111. Delhi: Parimal Publications, 2010.
Saṁghavī, Sukhlāljī; Pārīkh, Rasiklāl C., eds. Tattvopaplavasimha of Shri Jayarasi Bhatta. Edited with an introduction and indices. Gaekwad Oriental Series 87, Baroda: Oriental Institute, 1940; reprinted, Bauddha Bharati Series 20, Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1987.



[i] Eli Franco, Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarāśi’s Scepticism (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994; first published, Alt- und Neu-Indische Studien 35, Stuttgart Franz Steiner Verlag, 1987), modifies this assertion by calling Jayarāśi a skeptic Lokāyata rather than a materialist (xii–xiii), but very few pay attention to his distinction. They call Jayarāśi a Cārvāka or a Lokāyata, apparently meaning a materialist.
[ii] For instance, Vidyānandasvāmin, Aṣṭasahasrī (Mumbapuri: Nirnayasagara Press, 1915), 37: tadime tattvopaplavavādina … ; idem,Tattvārthaślokavārttika (Mumbapuri: Nirnayasagara Press, 1918), 80, 195; Anantavīrya, Siddhiviniścayaṭīkā (Kashi: Bharatiya Jnanapith, 1959), 277–278 all treat the Cārvāka and tattvopaplava-vāda separately. For a survey of the Jayarāśi controversy, see Piotr Balcerowicz, “Jayarāśi against the Philosophers,” this volume.
[iii] “Mukhavandha” (Foreword) to D. K. Mohanta, Tattvopaplavasiha: Jayarāśibhaṭṭer Saṃśayavāda (Kolkata: Sanskrita Sahitya Bhandar, 1998), [xiii].
[iv] Sukhlāljī Saghavī and Rasiklāl C. Pārīkh, eds., Tattvopaplavasimha of Shri Jayarasi Bhatta. Edited with an introduction and indices, Gaekwad Oriental Series 87, (Oriental Institute, Baroda 1940; reprinted, Bauddha Bharati Series 20, Varanasi 1987), 124.
[v] Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad, Indian Philosophy: A Popular Introduction (New Delhi: People’s Publishing House, 1965), 223. Even earlier, in two essays in Bangla published in 1963 (see his Sagha Śaraa Gacchami ityādi agranthita racanā [Kolkata: Ababhas, 2010] 74–84) Chattopadhyaya stated the same point.
[vi] M. K. Gangopadhyaya, “Mukhavandha,” [xi].
[vii] See W. H. S. Jones, Hippocrates, vol. 1 (London: William Heinemann, 1972), 8–9; T. W. Rhys Davids, Introduction, Mahānidānasuttanta, Dialogues of the Buddha (London: Oxford University Press, 1910), 47.
[viii] D. R. Shastri, A Short History of Indian Materialism, Sensationalism and Hedonism, in Cārvāka/Lokāyata, ed. D. Chattopadhyaya and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, 423.
[ix] For details see R. Bhattacharya, “The Case of Āryabhaa and His Detractors,” Indian Historical Review 17 (1990–1991): 35–47.
[x] T. Ganapati Shastri, The Arthaśāstra of Kaualya with the Śrīmūla Commentary (Dilli: Bharatiya Vidya Prakashan, 1984), 27.



Prof Ramkrishna Bhattacharya taught English at Unversity of Calcutta, Kolkota and was an Emeritus Fellow of University Grants Commission. He is now Fellow of Pavlov Institute, Kolkota



This essay is published in four parts: Part IPart II, Part III, & Part IV

Wednesday, 24 August 2016

Science versus Miracles: Curing Jaundice by Psychic Power

B. Premanand

The jaundice patient goes to the tantrik or godman for a cure. After an incantation over the medicine, the patient is administered the medicine. He asks the patient to gargle for a few minutes and then spit it out. When he spits out a yellow liquid, which looks like a bile, the tantrik says he has been cured.

Experiment: 143

Effect: Curing jaundice by psychic power.

Props: Mustard Oil.


Method: If you pour some mustard oil in your mouth and gargle for a few minutes and spit it out, it looks like brownish yellow liquid. This is because the oil gets emulsified with the saliva.

Saturday, 20 August 2016

Cārvāka: The Base Text and Its Commentators from the Eighth Century [A History of Materialism From Ajita to Udbhaṭa - Part III]

Ramkrishna Bhattacharya   


Cārvāka: The Base Text and Its Commentators from the Eighth Century

We now come to the formation of the philosophical systems, each having a set of aphorisms or sūtras with commentaries and sub-commentaries. Broadly speaking, the brahmanical position was unsparing in denouncing all the three of its non-Vedic adversaries, while the materialists had to put up a lone battle against all philosophical systems, Vedic and non-Vedic, but mostly against Buddhism, Jainism, Nyāya, and Vedānta. While the writings of the pre-Cārvāka materialist schools are unavailable, some fragments of the new, Cārvāka, school have come down to us. They can be divided into three kinds: (a) aphorisms (sūtras) and pseudo-aphorisms, (b) extracts from commentaries to the aphorisms, and (c) verses attributed to the Cārvākas[i]. The book of aphorisms was most probably compiled by Purandara, who is also credited with writing a short commentary (vṛtti). Besides the aphorisms that can be safely admitted as genuine, some others are of dubious authenticity. The distinction is made on the basis of the fact that some aphorisms are found quoted in several works with more or less the same wording. Those which occur only once may be marked as pseudo-aphorisms. The names of four commentators on the Cārvāka sūtras have so far come to light. They are Bhāvaviveka, Kambalāśvatara (“blanket-mule,” most probably a nickname), Aviddhakarṇa (“whose ear is not pierced,” probably another nickname), and Udbhaṭa-bhaṭṭa or Bhaṭṭodbhaṭa. That the Cārvāka system, very much like other systems, did not remain unaltered but saw its own development is borne out by the interpretation of some of the aphorisms offered by commentators in or around the eighth century[ii].

Udbhaṭa is the last of the commentators known to us. Jayanta and Cakradhara both speak of “old (cirantana) Cārvāka” and recent Cārvākas like Udbhaṭa. Udbhaṭa goes against the literal meaning of the aphorisms; he twists the meaning of words, which are made, almost under duress, to conform to the meanings preferred by him. In many respects he may be called a revisionist among the Cārvākas. However, what unites Purandara, Aviddhakarṇa, and Udbhaṭa is their assertion that, although inference based on perception can provide knowledge, inference based on authority (āpta) and verbal testimony (śabda or āptavākya) are inadmissible. So any statement concerning the existence of heaven and hell, god, an omniscient person, and so on is open to question. According to all of them, inference per se is not an independent instrument of cognition. Aviddhakarṇa and Udbhaṭa between themselves provide a number of arguments, both subtle and to the point, to establish this stand. Thus the extreme empiricism associated with older formulations of materialism is ameliorated by Cārvāka thinkers.

Here are the Cārvāka aphorisms (sūtras).

Materialism

I.1 We shall now explain the principle.
I.2 Earth, water, fire, and air are the principles, nothing else.
I.3 Their combination is called the “body,” “sense,” and “object.”
I.4 Consciousness (arises or is manifested) out of these.
I.5 As the power of intoxication (arises or is manifested from the constituent parts of the wine (such as flour, water, and molasses).
I.6 The self is (nothing but) the body endowed with consciousness.
I.7 From the body itself.
+ I.8 Because of the existence (of consciousness) where there is a body.
I.9 Souls are like water bubbles.

COMP Please provide line spacing here and for the below instances.?>

The doctrine of inherent nature (svabhāva; lit. own being)

II.1 The world is varied due to the variation of origin.
II.2 As the eye in the peacock’s tail.

The doctrine of the primacy of perception

III.1 Perception indeed is the (only) means of right knowledge.
III.2 Since the means of right knowledge is to be non-secondary, it is difficult to ascertain an object by means of inference.

The doctrine of the denial of rebirth and the other-world

IV.1 There is no means of knowledge for determining (the existence of) the other-world.
IV.2 There is no other-world because of the absence of any other-worldly being (i.e., the transmigrating self).
IV.3 Due to the insubstantiality of consciousness (residing in the other-world).

The doctrine of the uselessness of performing religious acts

V.1 Religious act is not to be performed.
V.2 Its (religion’s) instructions are not to be relied upon.

In addition to the aphorisms, verses, typically attributed to the pūraṇic Bṛhaspati, are mostly of the nature of what Patañjali would call “sung while intoxicated,” pramatta-gīta[iii]. Only three of the ten and half verses quoted by Mādhava in the Compendium of All Philosophies may be said properly to reflect the materialist view: 
There is no heaven, no final liberation, nor any soul in another world.Nor do the actions of the four castes, orders, etc., produce any real effect.While life remains let a man live happily; nothing is beyond death.When once the body becomes ashes, how can it ever return again?If he who departs from the body goes to another world,How is it that he comes not back again, restless for love of his kindred?[iv]

Mādhava refers to Bṛhaspati as the author of a number of verses that are found in the Viṣṇu Purāṇa and in Buddhist and Jaina sources[v]. Buddhists and Jainas share some of the views of the Cārvākas. As we have seen, all the three were branded “negativists” by Vedists. Dharmakīrti, conversely, says of Vedism/brahmanism, that “Belief in the authority of the Vedas, and in some creator (of the world), desiring merit from bathing, pride in (high) caste, and practicing self-denial for the eradication of sins—these five are the marks of stupidity of one whose intelligence is damaged.”[vi] All three groups oppose most particularly the performance of annual rituals for departed ancestors (śrāddha) and sacrificial rites (yajña) with a view to fulfilling one’s heart’s desire, both in this world and the next. But the opposition of the two religious communities on the one hand and the Cārvākas on the other arose from different reasons[vii]. The Cārvākas deny something that is axiomatic to the Buddhists and Jainas, the doctrines of karma and rebirth. Since Cārvākas do not consider philosophy to be a means of emancipation from the cycle of rebirth (mokṣa, mukti, or nirvāṇa) but view it as a practical guide to life, they incurred the wrath of all believers in the other-world, brahmanical or otherwise. The Cārvākas do not think in terms of the four aims of life (puruṣārthas), namely, religious merit (dharma), wealth (artha), pleasure (kāma), and freedom (mokṣa); and this too marks them apart from others.

What the opponents of the Cārvāka make them say regarding caste (varṇa) and women deserves attention. They are represented as being opposed to caste discrimination and in favor of the equality of women and men. This representation (censorial in intention) is borne out by the heretical views attributed to Kāli, personification of the Iron Age, in Śrīharṣa’s Life of Naiṣadha: 
Since purity of caste is possible only in the case of purity on each side of both families of the grandparents, what caste is pure by the purity of limitless generations? Fie on those who boast of family dignity! They hold women in check out of jealousy; but do not likewise restrain men, though the blindness of passion is common to both! Spurn all censorious statements about women as not worth a straw. Why dost thou constantly cheat people when thou, too, art as bad as women?[viii]

That this is not an isolated case or a mere figment of Śrīharṣa’s imagination is borne out by similar representations found elsewhere.[ix]

Cārvākas have often been accused of unrestrained hedonism. While such Buddhist, Jaina, and brahmanical opponents of the Lokāyata as Śāntarakṣita, Prabhācandra, and Śaṅkara preferred to controvert materialism solely on logical and epistemological grounds, some others condemned it for being licentious. It is worth noting that similar equation of materialism and hedonism has also been made in relation to Epicurus (341–270 BCE), though he is known to have led an extremely frugal life[x]. As with Epicurus, so with the Cārvākas: there is not an iota of evidence to prove that they used to preach an “eat, drink, and be merry” kind of philosophy, nor is there is a single aphorism that advises people to indulge in sensual gratification. As with Epicurus again, the Cārvākas might nevertheless have declared pleasure to be the aim of life. A popular verse runs as follows: 
While life is yours, live joyously;None can escape Death’s searching eye;When once this frame of ours they burn,How should it e’er again return?[xi]

We know from Epicurus’s own words that by pleasure he meant intellectual enjoyment, not eating and living like a pig—which is what Horace unjustly said of him. Jayanta, no friend of the Cārvākas, says of “Live joyously” that “being naturally established, a prescription in this regard becomes useless.”[xii] The available fragments of the commentaries on the Cārvāka-sūtra clearly reveal their authors’ acumen as logicians, and to think that they could lead the life of debauchees boggles the mind.





Bibliography

Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. Studies on the Cārvāka/Lokāyata. Firenze: Società Editriche Fiorentina, 2009; London: Anthem Press, 2011.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “The Social Outlook of the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Reconstruction.” Indologica Taurinensia 36 (2010): 37–42.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “The Wolf’s Footprints: Indian Materialism in Perspective.” Interview with Krishna Del Toso. Annali 71 (2011): 183–204.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “Svabhāvavāda and the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Historical Overview.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 40, no. 5 (2012): 593–614.
Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. “Verses Attributed to Bṛhaspati in the Sarvadarśanasaṃgraha: A Critical Appraisal.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 615–630.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad. In Defence of Materialism in Ancient India. New Delhi: People’s Publishing House, 1989.
Chattopadhyaya, Debiprasad, and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, eds. Cārvāka/Lokāyata. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990.
Dixit, K. K. “The Ideological Affiliation of Jayarāśi—The Author of Tattvopaplavasiṃha.” In Cārvāka/Lokāyata, edited by D. Chattopadhyaya and M. K. Gangopadhyaya, pp. 520–530. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990.
Franco, Eli: Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarāśi’s Scepticism. Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi 1994; 1st edition, Alt- und Neu-Indische Studien 35, Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1987.
Jayarāśibhaṭṭa. Tattvopaplavasiṃha of Jayarāśibhaṭṭa. Tr. Esther Solomon; ed. Shuchita Mehta: Jayarāśi Bhaṭṭa’s Tattvopaplavasiṁha. An Introduction, Sanskrit Text, English Translation and Notes. Parimal Sanskrit Series 111. Delhi: Parimal Publications, 2010.
Saṁghavī, Sukhlāljī; Pārīkh, Rasiklāl C., eds. Tattvopaplavasimha of Shri Jayarasi Bhatta. Edited with an introduction and indices. Gaekwad Oriental Series 87, Baroda: Oriental Institute, 1940; reprinted, Bauddha Bharati Series 20, Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1987.


[i] For details see R. Bhattacharya, Studies on the Cārvāka/Lokāyata, chap. 6.
[ii] Kamalaśīla, TSP verse 1864, mentions two approaches to the interpretation of an aphorism that contains no verb. One commentator supplied the verb “is born” after the subject, so that it reads “consciousness is born of these (elements),” while another commentator explained the same aphorism as “consciousness is manifested from these (elements).” Since Kamalaśīla uses the plural in case of both, it is not clear whether he means two individual commentators (the plural being honorific) or two groups of commentators (each group having some adherents of its own). As no names are mentioned it is impossible to decide who Kamalaśīla had in mind.
[iii] Kshitish Chandra Chatterji ed., Patañjali’s Mahābhāṣya. Paśpaśāhnika with English translation (Calcutta: A. Mukherjee & Co., 1972), K. V. Abhyankar and Jaydev Mohanlal Shukla ed., Patañjali’s VyakaraHa-Mahabha+ya, Ahnikas (Pune: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1975), 1–3. Patañjali, Mahābhāṣya, chap.1, Calcutta ed. 18, Pune ed. 13.
[iv] Sāyaa-Mādhava, Sarvadarśanasangraha. ed. K. L. Joshi. (Ahmedabad/Delhi: Parimal Publication, 1981), V. Shastri Abhyankar ed. (Pune: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1978) (reprint).
[v] See R. Bhattacharya, “Verses Attributed to Bhaspati in the Sarvadarśanasagraha: A Critical Appraisal,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 615–630.
[vi] Dharmakīrti, auto-commentary on the Pramāṇa-Vārttika, chap. 1 (Ilahabad: Kitab Mahal, 1943), 617–618.
[vii] Both the rites involved slaying of animals, which was anathema to the doctrine of non-injury (ahisā) of the Buddhists and the Jains. The Cārvākas too were opposed to postmortem rites, for they regarded them as useless (since there can be no life after death) and no benefit can accrue from the performance of yajñas, for there were no gods to grant the sacrificers’ prayers. In spite of all this, the two religious communities clung to the idea of rebirth, after-life (paraloka) and the mysterious effects of karman and adṛṣṭa.
[viii] Śrīhara, Life of Naiadha 17. 40, 42, 58. Naiadhacarita. ed. Sivadatta and V. L. Panshikar. (Mumbai: Nirnay Sagar Press, 1928). K. K. Handiqui trans. (Pune: Deccan College Postgraduate Research Institute, 1956).
[ix] For details see R. Bhattacharya, “The Social Outlook of the Cārvāka/Lokāyata: A Reconstruction,” Indologica Taurinensia 36 (2010): 37–42.
[x] Horace, Epistles 1.4.16 in Epistles (London: William Heinemann, 1926). See also Paul Harvey, Oxford Companion to Classical Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 162.
[xi] Mādhava, Compendium of All Philosophies. Pune ed., p. 2, lines 17–18.
[xii] Jayantabhaṭṭa, Nyāyamañjarī, part 1 (Varanasi: Sampurnanand Sanskrit Visvavidyalaya, 1982), 388, translated in Cārvāka/Lokāyata, ed. D. Chattopadhyaya and M. K. Gangopadhyaya (New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990), 157.



Prof Ramkrishna Bhattacharya taught English at Unversity of Calcutta, Kolkota and was an Emeritus Fellow of University Grants Commission. He is now Fellow of Pavlov Institute, Kolkota


This essay is published in four parts: Part I, Part II, Part III, & Part IV

Share

Twitter Delicious Facebook Digg Stumbleupon Favorites More